Published by Nova Publishers,
New York, 2016.
ISBN:
978-1-63482-407-1
The Politics of Cooperation and Co-ops: Forms of
Cooperation and Co-ops, and The Politics That Shape Them
Carl Ratner, Ph.D.
Institute for Cultural Research & Education
Trinidad, CA 95570
USA
http://www.sonic.net/~cr2
Abstract
This
book identifies political currents that underlie the organization and practices
of contemporary co-ops. The politics of co-ops and cooperation generate
distinctive, important insights into the characteristics of co-ops and the
reasons for them. Three currents of cooperative politics are identified:
populist politics, market politics, and capitalist politics. Extensive examples
of these cooperative politics are presented. They include the leading co-op
organizations such as the American National Cooperative Business Association,
and the International Cooperative Alliance, all the way down to local co-ops.
The
three cooperative politics that dominate the landscape of contemporary co-ops
are shown to be problematical. They are all inadequate to guide genuine,
complete cooperation. Their weaknesses are manifested in problematical
cooperative practices that shall be elucidated.
Because
co-op practice is grounded in political theory and practice, weaknesses in
cooperative practice must be overcome by implementing a new cooperative
politics. I articulate socialist politics of cooperation and co-ops as a
valuable candidate for this corrective . This politics
will be explained and assessed.
Table of Contents
Preface: Politics and politics
Introduction: Cooptation and Corruption in Social
Movements
Chapter One: Capitalist politics of Cooperation
and Co-ops
The Structure of The
Western International Cooperative Movement
The
International Cooperative Alliance
The National Cooperative Business Association
U.S. Agency for
International Development
National Cooperative Business AllianceÕs Neoliberal Employees
Purveying Capitalist Co-op Politics to The Grassroots
Credit
Unions, Capitalist Cooperative Politics, and NCBA
The
National Co-op Bank
Association of Cooperative Educators
The Texas Agricultural Cooperative Council
The Austin Cooperative Business Association
Recreational Equipment Inc. (REI)
Land
O'Lakes Dairy Co-op
The
National Council of Farmer Cooperatives
The
U.S. Overseas Cooperative Development Council
CHS Co-op
National
Rural Electric Cooperative Association
Federation
of Southern Co-ops
Conclusion
Chapter Two: Populist Politics of Cooperation and Co-ops
The International Cooperative AllianceÕs Statement
on Cooperative Identity
Flaws
in Populist Cooperative Politics
Formal
Democratic Management Does Not Equal Cooperation
Grassroots Economic Organizing Collective
Gar AlperovitzÕs Cooperative Proposals
Richard WolffÕs Populist, Socialist, Cooperativism
Postmodernizing Cooperativism and Socialism
The False Cultural Psychology of
Postmodernist Populism
The Red Herring of 20th Century
Socialism
Anti-Marxism in The Cooperative Movement
Can Co-ops Transform Capitalism and Bureaucratic
Socialism?
Solutions
Depend Upon Causes:
Looking Behind Co-op Problems to
Their Politics In Order to Look Ahead to Discover
Their Solution
Non-capitalist
Is Not Tantamount to Pro-socialist or Pro-cooperation
The Unnoticed, Unexplained
Shortcomings of Cooperation and Co-ops
Failed Populist, Postmodernist,
Politics in Movements for Social Transformation
The
Insidious Convergence of Populist and Capitalist politics of Cooperation and
Co-ops
Chapter Three: Toward A Socialist Politics of
Cooperation and Co-ops
The Illusion of Abstract,
Apolitical Cooperation
A
Socialist Politics Of Cooperation And Co-Ops Grounds
Cooperation and Co-Ops In A Socialist Mode Of Production, Or Socialist Political-Economy
MarxÕs
Critique of Capitalist Social Relations As The Basis
Of An Alternative Socialist Mode Of Production And Cooperation
MarxÕs
Alternative Socialist Mode of Production And
Cooperation As The Possible, Necessary, Viable Concrete Negation Of
Anti-Cooperation
MarxÕs
Analysis of Co-ops
Cooperative Psychology
MarxÕs Objectivistic
Theory of Socialist Cooperation
Actuality, Possibility And Necessity: A Philosophical Exegesis
Socialist Democracy Vs.
Populist Democracy
Levels of Cooperation
Chinese Socialist-Cooperative
Villages
References
Index
Preface
Politics and
politics
This
book argues that cooperation, like all social behavior, rests upon cultural
politics. That means that cooperation, like all social behavior, is rooted in
specific political values, ideals, objectives, and power relations concerning
the organizational form (structure) of social relations. Cooperators devise
cooperation and cooperatives to institutionalize particular forms of social
relations that are objectified externalizations and extensions of political
conceptions of freedom, rights, obligations, fulfillment, opportunity, social
participation, decision-making, power, sharing, privacy, sociality, the nature
of the individual, the relation of individual and sociality, modes of
government (governmentality) and social principles.
These
are political in the broad sense, not in the narrow sense of political parties.
Politics is far broader than simply Democrat, Republican, Christian Democrat,
Labor Party, Social Democrat, etc. For the sake of clarity, we may designate
formal politics in political parties as Politics (with a capital P), while
broad, general politics is designated with a small p.
Foucault (2014, chap. 1)
employed this approach in defining the term government.
He distinguished formal Government from government Òbeing understood, of
course, not in the narrow and current sense of the supreme authority of
executive and administrative decisions in the statist systems, but in the large
sense, and the old [sense] of the mechanisms and procedures intended to conduct
men, to direct the conduct of men, to conduct the conduct of men.Ó
FoucaultÕs ideas
underlie this book. For Foucault emphasized that the ways of thinking about
issues tacitly rest upon and promulgate political concerns, a political
rationality, a political logic, or a political a priori (Miller &
Rose, 2008, chapter 2). That is exactly the point of this book: to elucidate
the politics of the way cooperation is conceptualized and practiced in co-ops.
Conceptions and practices of co-ops are neither natural, universal, or purely
intellectual (i.e., neutral). They are stimulated by, organized by, and
functional for particular political concerns and rationality. Understanding and
changing particular forms of cooperation and co-ops requires understanding and
changing their underlying political rationalities Ð that are rooted in
political economy. In other words, the political rationality of co-op praxes
reinforces a corresponding political-economy. This is a vital insight into
understanding the potential that any particular co-op praxis has for
emancipating people from the status quo. Since genuine, fulfilling, viable
cooperation and co-ops require a new political economy that negates the
anti-cooperative features of the status quo, the politics of cooperation and
co-ops are powerful indicators of their capacity to achieve genuine cooperation
and co-ops.
American cooperation and cooperatives are
motivated and guided by politics, not usually by Politics. (The Italian case is
rather different. Until recently, Italian co-ops were associated with the Communist
Party and the Catholic Church. Ratner, 2013). The absence of Politics from the
movement does not imply an absence of politics. Cooperators sometimes conflate
these, and believe that cooperation is apolitical altogether. This is false. It
obfuscates the broad politics that organize and direct cooperation and co-ops.
It leaves cooperators influenced by powerful politics that they do not realize
and cannot control.
Because
the political basis of cooperative politics does not originate internally to them,
but rather in the political system in which they function, improving
cooperative politics requires transforming the political system that forms
them. Co-op reform thus requires broad societal reform, focusing upon the
political-economic core of society. Co-ops and cooperation cannot be enhanced
via internal, technical adjustments.
My
political analysis of cooperation and co-ops resonates with Naomi KleinÕs
analysis of environmental policy (Klein, 2014). She traces climate policy to
politics, and she traces inadequacies in climate policy to exploitive political
economics in the worldÕs countries today. She emphasizes that genuine change in
climate policy -- that will make human life sustainable in the future --
requires transformation of the political-economies of the worldÕs countries.
Failing this, the given political economics will continue to generate
environmentally destructive policies. Exactly the same is true for cooperation
and cooperatives. Her subtitle: ÒCapitalism vs. the ClimateÓ can be paraphrased
as ÒCapitalism vs. Cooperation.Ó Capitalism prevents cooperation, and this
antagonism requires that capitalism be transformed in order to effect
cooperation, just as it must be transformed in order to effect a humanly
sustainable ecological system. Anti-cooperation cannot be solved within
capitalism because it is a product of capitalism (as well as virtually all
other social systems today). Anti-cooperation is a structural problem of
capitalism which logically requires a structural change in capitalism.
The
movement for cooperation and climate sustainability are not simply parallel
with regard to the causes and solutions of the different problems; the
movements are organically linked. Klein argues that the political-economic
transformation necessary for sustainable climate policy and practice is the
same transformation that is necessary for a cooperative society: solving
pollution requires a cooperative political economy that is owned and controlled
by the citizens rather than by corporate executives. This makes her analysis of
climate policy/practice inextricably related to my analysis of cooperative
policy/practice.
Klein
criticizes major environmental groups which act as though technical changes can
save the environment, without the need for restructuring the political economy.
She argues that they abet environmental destruction by denying the necessary
political changes necessary to stop it.
Likewise, major cooperative groups act as though cooperation can be
constructed within the parameters of capitalism, to co-exist with capitalism.
This makes them an impediment to cooperation because they deny the political
action necessary to realize it.
I
shall use a political analysis to analyze and critique the contemporary
cooperative movement in the U.S. In other words, I shall link the concrete
quality of cooperation and cooperatives to their implicit political conceptions
of freedom, human rights, fulfillment, opportunity, social participation,
decision-making, power, sociality, the nature of the individual, and modes of
government.
Mine
is the only political analysis of cooperation and co-ops. It offers
unique insights into the practice, problems, and avenues for the advance of
cooperation and co-ops. My analysis derives from my book Macro Cultural Psychology:
A Political Philosophy of Mind (2012) that analyzes the political
foundations of psychological phenomena and the discipline of Psychology.
The co-op movement seeks to be a
structural alternative to capitalism. It seeks to develop new forms of economic
ownership and management, social responsibility, and sustainable use of natural
resources. I ask whether co-ops in their current direction and organization can
accomplish this task. In Foucauldian terminology, I problematize co-ops as a
form of social organization or governance.
I demonstrate that the current,
predominant organizations (and conceptual ideals) of co-ops are incapable of
realizing cooperative, progressive ideals. Despite their good intentions to
implement economic democracy, social responsibility, and ecological
sustainability, local co-ops and powerful co-op associations have adopted
conservative, reformist politics that are complicit with political and economic
institutions of capitalism. These politics may be dubbed 1) capitalist cooperative
politics, 2) market cooperative politics, and 3) populist cooperative politics.
Capitalist
cooperative politics are practices by
co-op organizations that collaborate and partner with capitalist corporations
and their government agencies such as the State Department. Capitalist politics
subordinate co-ops activities to capitalist corporations, merge with capitalist
corporations, hire corporate and governmental officials, allow corporations to
infiltrate cooperative associations and even write co-op policies, and take on
the form of capitalist corporations. Capitalist cooperative politics thusly
generate a degraded form of cooperation and co-ops. Yet capitalist politics
dominate the cooperative movement, as I shall prove in chapter one. Capitalist
cooperative politics refer to the practices that these co-ops engage in. I call
this kind of cooperation Òneoliberal cooperation.Ó
Yet
the co-ops that practice capitalist cooperative politics are not capitalist
organizations. They are not owned and controlled by capitalists and
investors for their private enrichment. The irony of capitalist co-ops is that
they are technically co-ops that abide by cooperative principles Ð of each
member owning one share and having one (equal) vote on policy matters, and
receiving no significant financial enrichment from their single share. The
irony is that these co-ops practice capitalist kinds of activities. They pay
their CEOs $6 million compensation packages, they lobby against environmental
regulations, they produce genetically modified food, their executives are drawn
from notorious capitalist companies such as Monsanto, they contribute to
reactionary politicians, they accept funding from capitalist government
agencies such as U.S. Agency for International Development, they endorse these
agencies, and they partner with capitalist agencies and corporations on many
projects. They invite them to underwrite co-op conferences, sponsor them, and
write documents for the co-op movement. These capitalist practices are often
difficult to criticize for they occur under the banner of cooperation and
co-ops.
It
is important to keep in mind the distinction between capitalist co-ops,
and capitalist corporations that are owned and controlled by
capitalists, and operate according to capitalist economic principles.
Market
cooperative politics are expressed in
the phrase Òmarkets without capitalism.Ó This denotes commodity production and
exchange among producers and consumers, without capitalists owning and
controlling enterprises and exploiting employees and expropriating the
surpluses they produce. I have discussed market politics in my previous book
(Ratner, 2013, pp. 109-132). I therefore do not discuss them here, although I
do review some of that material. Suffice it to say that I have found market
cooperative politics to be plagued with the alienation and instability of
market political-economy that Marx criticized. Market cooperative politics
generate a degraded form of cooperation and co-ops.
Populist
cooperative politics advocate common
people coming together to collectively and democratically meeting their needs.
It is a form of Òpeople powerÓ where people own and control institutions and
figure out how to solve problems and meet their own needs. Co-ops are the main
devices for accomplishing these populist objectives. Co-ops are defined as
"an autonomous association of persons united voluntarily to meet their
common economic, social, and cultural needs and aspirations through a jointly
owned and democratically controlled enterpriseÓ (ÒThe Statement on the
Co-operative IdentityÓ by the International Cooperative Alliance in 1995).
I
shall demonstrate that populist cooperative politics have eliminated the worst
excesses of capitalist exploitation in their small enclaves. However, they do
not challenge the dominance of the anti-cooperative social system, which leaves
co-ops and the populace constrained by the dominant system.
Because
these three cooperative politics are insufficient to generate genuine,
fulfilling cooperation, a fourth cooperative politics is necessary to
accomplish this: 4) socialist politics.
Socialist
cooperative politics champion a
thorough critique of class society and a concrete negation of it as the basis
of cooperation. Cooperation is grounded in a socialist mode of production and
embodies its social relations. This eliminates the anti-cooperative social
system that negates cooperation. It provides the social and material and
philosophical basis for establishing a cooperative mode of production. Socialist
politics generate a concrete, viable, fulfilling cooperation that populist
politics, market politics, and capitalist politics do not. Socialist
cooperative politics take their lead from MarxÕs statement: In chapter five of The Civil War in France: "if co-operative production is not to remain a sham and a snare; if it is
to supersede the capitalist system; if united co-operative societies are to
regulate national production upon a common plan, thus taking it under their own
control and putting an end to the constant anarchy and periodical convulsions
which are the fatality of capitalist production, what else, gentlemen, would it
be but communism?" (http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1871/civil-war-france/ch05.htm)
My
critique of the three existing politics of cooperation and co-ops (capitalist,
market, and populist) does not say that they do no good. They do good in
limited ways. They assuage some of the destructiveness that capitalist wreaks
around the world. They palliate its problems. Cooperatives provide better
working conditions than private firms do; they treat the environment much
better; they provide better quality, organic goods; they engage in stable,
secure business practices (for the most part Ð e.g., they suffered far less
than corporate banks and businesses during the recession, and they did not
cause the recession in contrast to capitalist institutions which did); and they
provide some opportunities for marginalized people to raise their standard of
living. These advantages are admirable. They prove that non-capitalist
socioeconomic relations are viable and beneficial. Marx & Engels praised
co-ops for this: ÒWe acknowledge the co-operative movement as one of the
transforming forces of the present society based upon class antagonism. Its
great merit is to practically show, that the present pauperising, and despotic
system of the subordination of
labour to capital can be
superseded by the republican and beneficent system of the association of free and equal
producersÓ (http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/iwma/documents/1866/instructions.htm).
However,
the benefits of co-ops are small and inadequate relative to the breadth and
depth of social problems that need correcting. These inadequacies are due to
inadequate politics.
Politics
are structuring structures of behavior, in BourdieuÕs words. They embody a
logic that drives behavior in particular directions and away from other directions.
They animate certain behavior and they impede, or resist, other, contradictory
behavior. They provide coherence to behavior, they explain behavior, and they
are the mechanisms of behavior. (Politics also structure the way in which
people understand behavior, as in the discipline of Psychology.) Politics
are important psychological constructs (Ratner, 2012, 2015a, b, c).
The
logic of politics means that logic is an ontology, logic is ontological, a real force that drives behavior. Logic
does not act on its own, of course. Logic is the requirements that must be met by
people in order to maintain the politics that are useful to them. If people
want to develop fulfilling cooperation they must apprehend the logic of
socialist cooperative politics, which are the corresponding social relations,
concepts/values, and conditions. that they require, represent, and advance. And
these socialist cooperators must oppose contradictory politics, social
relations, conditions, and concepts/values. The same holds for the other three
politics of cooperation and co-ops.
The
ontological logic of politics leads to continually asking why behaviors occur.
When a cooperator acts uncooperatively we look for the logic that generated it.
ÒWhy would the International Cooperative Alliance write co-op principles in
that way?Ó ÒWhat kind of politics do these principles represent and benefit?Ó
ÒWhy would the International Cooperative Alliance invite a conservative
militarist like Secretary of State Madeleine Albright to address a Co-op Summit?Ó
What political values and interests do this represent?Ó Why do populist co-ops
reject Marxism and socialism? ÒWhy would the International Cooperative Alliance
invite a corporate criminal like Ernst & Young to sponsor a Co-op Summit
and write a document about cooperative issues?Ó ÒWhy would the National
Cooperative Business Association honor the CEO of a producer co-op that
perpetrates capitalist-type activities and crimes, and partners with corporate
criminals and polluters?Ó ÒWhat kinds of political interests and values does
this represent?Ó ÒWhy would NCBA partner with a corrupt, imperialist agency
such as US Agency for International Development?Ó ÒWhat is the logical
connection between these? Conversely, ÒWhy do USAID, Albright, and corporate
criminals partner with co-op organizations such as ICA and NCBA? What do they
find appealing about co-ops?Ó What is the logical connection here?
A
political perspective on co-ops and cooperation does not treat anti-cooperative
acts as isolated, ignorant mistakes that are readily corrected by some training
or sensitivity or Òdialogue.Ó We search for their logical, rational causes that
are deeply rooted in fundamental politics. These politics make uncooperative
behavior functional for certain political ends, and they make
uncooperative behavior necessary to achieve those ends. Elucidating the
political logic of anti-cooperative behavior provides us with the most
rigorous explanation. This may be
called the politics of cooptation and corruption. It is elucidated in this
book through a hermeneutic of cooptation and corruption.
Elucidating
the political logic of anti-cooperative behavior is also the clue to
changing it. It can only be changed by thoroughly rejecting those politics and
adopting alternative politics of cooperation whose logic embodies and
leads to cooperation. And this new politics of cooperation must be rooted in
structural changes in the political economy. This shall be revealed through a hermeneutic
of genuine cooperation.
This
political analysis of cooperation and anti-cooperation has value for
understanding and changing all behavior. Consider the rampant police brutality
against the poor and especially poor minorities. We ask what is the political
logic of this? What are the political interests the require this and benefit
from it, and make it functional. We look at the ways
it is institutionalized in laws, codes, training, and the availability of
cultural artifacts such as surveillance cameras and military weapons for
police. We look for how it is embedded in the social structure and how it
emanates from that structure and how it is functional for maintaining that
structure. We also elucidate fundamental changes to the structure and its
politics that are required to eliminate police brutality. We do not treat the
problem as rooted in psychological dispositions such as police aggressiveness,
or police feelings of threat from indigent people, or police lack of
understanding of the poor and their customs. Nor do we accept personalized
solutions such as sensitivity training for police, or dialogue between police
and poor minorities in order to increase mutual understanding (which
makes the victims equally responsible for police brutality). All of these
personalized causes and solutions overlook and obfuscate the real, objective,
systemic, structural political interests that are the cause and the solution.
It is not a matter of dialoguing to creatively discover novel solutions. It is
a matter of presenting demands that are based upon objective analysis of the
structural politics of police brutality.
The
contradiction of liberal reformism
Conventional cooperation and co-ops epitomize the contradiction of
liberal reformism: reformism is valuable compared to the status quo, however,
it is obstructionist and obscurantist to full, genuine emancipation. It is not
simply incomplete change that can be extended; rather, liberalism resists the praxis
of a complete emancipation. Liberal reformism is a strategy of the status quo
that sustains the status quo by adding a small humanistic element. It never
seeks to transform the system. This why it is ultimately acceptable to the
system. Liberals often attack radicals who wish to negate or supersede the
capitalist mode of production. Radicalism is not a continuous, quantitative
extension of liberalism. It is qualitatively different political philosophy.
Liberalism is not simply a stunted form of social change that needs a little
push to move it further along to deeper change. Liberals must learn a new
social philosophy in order to support social transformation.
This is true within the co-op movement. Current
co-ops are liberal reformists. They do not challenge the State and leading
capitalist institutions. They are largely apolitical, as I shall demonstrate in
chapter two. In this sense co-ops renounce and denounce strategies and
objectives that are necessary for social transformation. The fact that co-ops
are acceptable to the status quo indicates that their version of cooperation is
more conservative than it is transformative and emancipatory. This failure to
challenge the status quo is why co-ops have been incapable of achieving genuine
cooperation.
For genuine, fulfilling,
liberating cooperation to be implemented, the character of cooperation must
become radical, militant, and oppositional to the anti-cooperative status quo.
Cooperation must be developed as a radical mode of cooperation within a
radical-cooperative mode of production that is based upon a socialist
politics of cooperation and co-ops. That is the theme of this book.